Luke Matthews, PhD
  • Home
  • Publications and Research
  • Blog

Does it matter if we are all African?

10/13/2012

4 Comments

 
Research out last August by Anders Eriksson and Andrea Manica made news in the press for contradicting claims of neanderthal ancestry in contemporary humans.  This research is completely driven by mathematical modeling rather than relying on empirical data, and I think ultimately Neanderthal admixture will be supported.  John Hawks has very capably laid out the scientific issues and the reasons why Neanderthal admixture is likely to be supported when all is said and done.  What I want to address in this blog are the moral lessons that some have tried to extract from the “out of Africa” explanation of human origins.  Considering these past arguments in light of the currently debated genetic evidence for Neanderthal admixture indicates why arguments for the equal treatment of people based on their common origin are dangerous rhetoric passed off as reasoned philosophy.

The history of the argument that we should all treat each other equally because we are all so genetically similar or because we share a common ancestry in Africa dates back at least a dozen years.  In an article that appeared in the New York Times, writer Nicholas Wade quoted Harvard biologist Edward O. Wilson as saying “We need to create a new epic based on the origins of humanity” (Wade 2000).  Dr. Wilson’s comments came from another article in the Wall Street Journal, in which he indicated that the evolutionary history of Homo sapiens could be a new basis for spiritual values that could replace traditional religion.  Mr. Wade’s own commentary from his article was that: “Many of the biologists who are reconstructing the human past certainly believe their work has a value that transcends genetics. Although their lineage trees are based on genetic differences, most of these differences lie in the regions of DNA that do not code for genes and have no effect on the body.”  He then quoted Dr. Peter Underhill, a geneticist who studies human origins as saying, "We are all Africans at the Y chromosome level and we are really all brothers."

Isn’t it convenient when scientific knowledge of the way the world is seems to justify how we think the world ought to be?  In this case people were arguing from evidence of the way biological variation originated in our species (world is) as a reason for why human behavior should be equitable across racial distinctions (world ought to be).  Trouble eventually follows though when people start saying the reason we ought to behave a certain way is because the world is a certain way.  As the out of Africa model gained more empirical support, even more scientists wanted to jump on the band wagon because they thought they had found a home-run secular reason to justify the equal treatment across race lines that had always been argued on theistic grounds from the time of the Abraham Lincoln and the abolitionists to Martin Luther King Jr. and the civil rights movement.  Searching online can find plenty of comments from anthropologists about how human biological variation is only ‘skin deep’ and we are all very recently diverged – as if racism would be more OK if biological differences went deeper than skin level or they diverged more anciently?  By 2010 Richard Dawkins was giving talks to forums for the black community about how “we are all African,” and even selling T-shirts! 

It was Christopher diCarlo, however, who laid out the case most explicitly that we all should treat each other well because of the facts of our origins in 2010 in Free Inquiry.  Dr. diCarlo does an admirable job of laying out the known science of human evolution.  Intriguingly, one of the scientists he covers prominently is Andrea Manica.  He summarizes the state of the science with: “We are all African. With these four words, we see a genetic coalescence of the entire human population. We now know that we descended from inhabitants of Africa who began migrating out of Africa around 60,000 years ago. In this way, it is impossible for us to not all be, in some ways, related.”  He then continues to draw philosophical lessons from this: “With these four words [we are all African], we see that racism is a human invention.  It is a social construct with lingering natural biases—leftover baggage from our mammalian xenophobic tendencies.”

I suppose then the proverbial shoe fell in May 2010 when scientists apparently confirmed that at least all living non-African humans have some Neanderthal ancestry that is not shared by African humans (here I use African in the idiomatic English language meaning rather than the sense of Dr. Dawkin’s linguistic contortion).  Yes, the percentage is small.  The original Neanderthal genome article put the value at 1-4% Neanderthal genes for non-Africans, but more recent studies indicate that number might rise to 8% summed admixture from Neanderthals and Homo erectus for some of us.  So, 8% non-recent African origin is small, but it certainly seems nontrivial.  Does that mean Dr. diCarlo now should conclude that racism is less of a ‘human invention’ or that some racism is more functional than ‘leftover baggage’?  Should we now start making T-shirts for Africans that say things like “Racially pure, no Neanderthal in here” or the Caucasian version “1-4% Neanderthal and loving it.”  If all Dr. Dawkins was doing with his T-shirt was educating the public about science then I suppose these post-neanderthal genome T-shirts are equally valid?  I hope he sends me a note when he starts selling them at his online store.

Of course Dr. Dawkins wasn’t just talking about science.  He and Dr. diCarlo were trying, poorly, to justify their deeply held ethical belief that equal treatment of people from different human subpopulations is a moral imperative.  For hardline atheists like these thinkers, the traditional theistic and metaphysical justifications on which abolition and civil rights were based are off the table.  They can’t believe as theists do that we should all treat each other equally because we emulate the God who knows and loves everyone regardless of the particulars of their traits or origins.  They don’t buy into the metaphysical claims of many Enlightenment thinkers that people are endowed with inherent rights that do not arise from natural origins.  Thus Drs. Dawkins, diCarlo and others predicated moral truth on empirical truth of our natural origins.  If they sincerely meant any of what they said, then they have to conclude racial prejudice is now a little more permissible (on the order of at least 1-4% more permissible). 

Alternatively, they could admit what I suspect is the case, that they never actually thought these arguments from peoples’ origins being equal were good justifications for people treating each other equally.  Admitting that however, would be tantamount to admitting that they don’t have a justification for their moral claims.  It would also mean admitting that instead of searching for good justifications for their moral claims, they would rather pass off glib rhetoric as reasons to their audience, apparently confident that their audience wouldn’t see that these are terribly illogical arguments, and therefore dangerous arguments, for equal treatment of human persons.

I suspect the current debate about human origins will land on the conclusion that some living humans exhibit some degree of genetic admixture from Neanderthals.  The result of this debate has many important scientific implications, but for those of us who hold to the reasons our culture has always held for equal treatment there are no ethical implications of this research.  From the many founding fathers of the United States who objected to slavery at our country’s infancy, to Abraham Lincoln and Martin Luther King Jr., our culture has always used some form of metaphysical argument, and usually a theistic one, to justify that people from different ‘races’ should be treated equally.  The theistic justification is a strong one precisely because it does not depend on any of the facts of what our origins, similarities, or differences may be. 

Wade, N. 2000. The human family tree: 10 Adams and 18 Eves. The New York Times. May 2, 2000, Tuesday, Late Edition – Final. Section F; Page 1; Column 1.

4 Comments

If selection is on individuals, why aren't the selfish mutants taking over?

9/26/2012

8 Comments

 
I've followed the literature and debates on the evolution of cooperation since the beginning of my graduate schooling.  Central to these debates is the role played by group structure in allowing altruistic cooperation to evolve, and whether it deserves to be called group selection.  What we call it is a semantic issue, but in their take-down of group selection, people like Richard Dawkins and Steven Pinker have misrepresented the evolutionary mechanisms for group selection.  The key misrepresentation is that selection only acts on individuals or genes, and that there is no value added to thinking about groups.

First, we have to be clear what this debate is about.  The only type of cooperation that matters in this debate is classically called 'evolutionary altruism.'  This means a behavior that has a real fitness cost to the actor who performs the behavior.  Doing the behavior itself is costly, such that it would be eliminated by natural selection if not for direct fitness benefits acquired by the recipient.  However, for any behavior to evolve that benefits only the recipient and not the actor, then there has to be a mechanism by which the recipients of the behavior also tend to be those who perform the behavior as well.  Otherwise there will be 'freeriders' who game the system by collecting benefits as recipients, but because they never perform the behavior they will never pay the costs.  Essentially all models for how evolutionary altruism can evolve are just mechanisms that effectively cut these freeriders out of being recipients, such that recipients are more likely to be also performers of the behavior.  The equation that formalizes the rigor with which the mechanism must exclude freeriders is W.D. Hamilton's famous formulation for inclusive fitness, which describes how the relatedness must exceed the ratio of the cost of performing the behavior over the benefit of receiving it.  r > c/b (see Nowak 2006).  r measures recent genealogical relatedness, in this case, and is one mechanism to ensure that the recipient has at least  probability = r of having the genes that cause the individual to perform the altruistic behavior.

That's the mathematical kernal - now enter decades of semantic nutshells around this.  Does altruism evolve because of group selection, or is it because individuals are gaining 'indirect' fitness benefits for themselves, or is it really genes promoting copies of themselves residing in the bodies of other individuals?  People like Dr. Dawkins and Dr. Pinker have been consistent and vociferous in their denial of any group selection going on in the evolution of altruism.  Here are some thought experiments that are troubling for this assertion:

1.  Consider an evolutionarily altruistic behavior that has evolved by kin selection.  For this behaivor, individuals recognize siblings and then perform a fitness-costly behavior that benefits the sibling.  Siblings have an r=0.5, which satisfies Hamilton's equation for this particular behavior, but assume relatedness lower than 0.4 does not.  So far so good.  Now, our individual selectionists will point to the benefits being given to relatives and say 'see - indirect benefits to the actors - ergo, no group selection effects.'  But what happens when a freerider mutant who never performs the behavior is born into an altruist family?  There is no reciprocity in this system, meaning the mutant's siblings just detect that he is their sibling and thus donates the benefits to him.  What happens?  The freerider mutant always will have a higher fitness than his siblings, because he never pays the cost of the behavior and he receives just as many benefits.  If the only thing we need to think about is the relative fitness of individuals, then kin selection cannot evolve altruistic behaviors because freerider mutants always have higher fitness than their altruistic siblings.  How can the gene for the altuistic behavior ever prosper?  Clearly within their own families, altruists always lose to freeriders.
    If you are a scientist whose thinking has been dogmatized against group selection, don't worry, there's hope.  Just each morning keep repeating the freerider (saying selfish is more fun) mutant scenario, and it will help to deprogram you.  This is what I had to go through to really understand this after years of programming.  Just keep saying, but what about the fact that freerider (selfish) mutants always have to have higher fitnesses within their own families?! 
    The reason Hamilton's equation actually works is because freerider mutants go on to have families that are dominated by sets of freeriders.  That's the only way it can work.  Once this happens, the payoff to selfishness drops below altruism because now the selfish individuals get none of the benefits of the behavior (none of their siblings perform the behavior).  Hamilton himself identified this very clearly in his 1975 book chapter in the volume "Biosocial Anthropology".  Try reading it in addition to Hamilton's 1964 (here is the first one of the pair).
    David S. Wilson has argued, and I agree, that the best way to think about and phrase this insight is that evolutionary altruism evolves because of across-group fitness differentials.  The reason Hamilton's equation works is because a sufficient level of recent genealogical inheritance will create enough across group fitness differential to overcome the invasion of freerider mutants.  Should we call this group selection?  Seems reasonable to me, but we could call it other things.  It differs from traits that we could properly say are selected only at the individual level because the fitness differential that causes the gene to increase in frequency only occurs across some sets of individuals in the population (in my scenario these sets are individuals across different kin groups).  Indeed, this is why Hamilton himself suggested in 1975 that it would be clearer to call some inclusive fitness effects as kin-group selection.  I like this term a lot actually.  We could also make the distinction by talking about selection that is within-group and within-population as different from selection that is within-population only.  That might be most pleasing to the likes of Drs. Dawkins and Pinker, as now we would only by implication be saying something happens at a group level.  It's completely correct - kin selected evolutionary altruism is not selectively favored within groups of kin.  Any claim that it is so selected is demonstrably, devastatingly, false.  Hamilton shows this very clearly in his 1975 chapter.  Within-group within-population is a bit wordy though, so we would have to make acronyms out of them and distinguish between WGWP and WP forms of selection.  Seems cumbersome, but again, we humans make up these semantics so we can call it what ever we like.


2.  OK, so after thought experiment 1 a now wavering anti-group-selectionist might be thinking 'well fine, but that scenario didn't change any of the actual predictions of my incorrect individual selection verbiage.  So, even if I was right for the wrong reasons, I still got the right predictions, which is what matters in science.'  That's quite fair, and I agree wholeheartedly that getting the right predictions is what matters in science.  Once we give up on this we become philosophers, and we had those for thousands of years and never figured out anything. 
    But individual selection thinking does get predictions wrong.  One prediction that gets missed every time without thinking about groups is the distinction between an altruistic behavior that by its nature is a public good (perhaps an alarm call to my whole group) from one that relies on kin recognition mechanisms.  In the former, there is no point in evolving kin recognition and the r that matters is the average r of the group.  The fact that the alarm call warns siblings, for example, has to be discounted by the fact that it warns nonrelated individuals, and the discounting comes out to exactly the mean r across the group that hears the alarm call.  This is a serious prediction that in my experience with students and colleagues gets missed all the time and, again, is very well laid out in Hamilton's 1975 paper (and also by the way it is in the 1964 paper).  Sure, you can rephrase how kin selection works on public good in inclusive fitness terms if you want, but the correct predictions do not flow naturally from this logic and I think are frequently missed by empirical researchers.

3.    Let's continue to where things continue to get worse for anti-group-selection views when we think more about gene-eye-views of the world.
    Are genes the unit of selection?  I have no doubt they are a unit of inheritance, but selection?  The only way they can be a unit of selection is if you adopt a very contorted notion of what a gene is.  Let me illustrate.  Imagine two villages of humans that each are involved in reciprocal altruism within the village - you scratch my back and I'll scratch yours.  So, now the individuals stop giving benefits to freeriders after they discover through their interactions who is a freerider.  Let's suppose one village all have the same gene variants (alleles) that cause them to behave with altuistic reciprocity, but the other village is like a UN training camp with people from all over the world.  Just by chance, the UN village has different alleles that have different base pair sequences.  They all equally produce the same altruistic reciprocity behavior, but they are different sequences, and they have different evolutionary origins.  Maybe some of them even differ in functional parts of the allele that contribute to reciprocal altruism, and maybe in fact some people's reciprocity behavior is influence by different sections of DNA that are not even orthologous to the sections that affect another's reciprocity.  Even though they create the same phenotype, would anyone really call these the same 'genes'?  With their different origins and different sequences can they be said to be the same 'entities' selfishly advancing 'their' own replication?  It seems to me they are not, and remember the village with all the same homologous reciprocity inducing alleles with the exact same base pair sequences!  Any natural interpretation of the English language would conclude that there is more successfully selfish genic selection for reciprocity happening in the homogenous village.  I mean, the UN village is benefiting copies of other genes that aren't even remotely related to each other. 
    The point is none of this 'gene's eye view' and 'selfishly replicating genes' stuff matters.  Evolution, remember, is just a set of mundane mechanistic interactions that stack up to produce algorithmic effects over time.  Think of it like a set of billiard balls being hit ever so deterministically on a table, but instead of the balls moving across space the chains of causal collisions are moving through time.  It doesn't matter whether these alleles had the same origin, different origin, or even if they are in the same places on chromosomes or code for the same protein products.  All that matters is they cause the individuals to do this reciprocal behavior with other reciprocal individuals, so all these diverse genes involved in such a system can rise with the other's tides.  I think somewhere Dr. Dawkins tried to redefine individual selfish genes as just this highly abstract entity, such that we would call different nonorthologous stretches of DNA and different nonhomologous alleles all one 'gene' if they were all related to a single phenotype.  But no one actually defines 'a gene' this way because it would make doing human genomes, and biochemistry, and most of biology impossible. 

After these thought experiments hopefully you have loosened up to see the key to evolutionary altruism is just to find any mechanism where the benefits of altruistic action keep getting to other altruists and freeriders are excluded.  Any mechanism that reliably establishes a correlation between being an altruist and receiving benefits from other altruists will do - it doesn't have to achieve this at every grouping level of society, and it doesn't have to do it through homologous genes that selfishly replicate themselves.  In fact, it doesn't need genes at all, just inherited stuff.  Now the predictions really start to diverge from typical gene and individual selectionist theory.  Because if you just need inherited stuff, then evolution can use cultural variants as well to create evolutionarily altruistic adaptations.  That's a topic for another blog (here is my recent paper on it), and I hate to say this one more time, but yes, W.D. Hamilton already identified how cultural evolution would work equally well for all this in his 1975 chapter.   
8 Comments

What is anthropology?

9/24/2012

1 Comment

 
I think my experience is not unusual among anthropologists that I am often asked what anthropology is?  This question usually implies what makes anthropology a distinct discipline; that is, what makes it different from evolutionary biology or sociology?

Through teaching and multiple interactions with colleagues, I've found the best answer to this question of what anthropology is involves understanding a little about how anthropology came about.  Anthropology is essentially a natural science discipline.  It came about at a time when many natural history type disciplines arose.  As we discovered the incredible diversity of natural life in the 18th and 19th centuries, scientists began to specialize on particular taxonomic groups of related organisms.  Thus we started to have mammalogists and herpetologists and so forth.  After Darwin we had a fully viable mechanism for how all the diversity of life could be linked together in a single unbroken and absolutely continuous history.  Anthropology was born of the realization that this same unbroken character of evolutionary history must apply to humans; that all the incredible biological and cultural diversity of our species arose from a less diverse origin, and that it came about through evolutionary processes.  Since we are humans, it seemed reasonable that there should be a natural history science about ourselves.  Hence anthropology.

Because anthropology was born of the mindset of naturalists pursuing science, it made sense to early anthropologists like Edward Tylor and Louis H. Morgan that anthropology would pursue both a survey of extant cultural diversity and would investigate the archeological and fossil record of human existence as part of one discipline.  This is, after all, exactly how a natural historian of the time would attempt to understand the evolutionary diversification of a related group of fish or rodents.  You would want to know the existing diversity, about which you can of course have much more detailed information, but then also be linking that as much as possible to the direct evidence of past evolutionary change from the fossil record.  Comparison and comparative methods have always been key to the study of evolution in any set of organisms.  Indeed, comparison across many geographic scales, comparison among extant species, and comparison to the fossil record were all key sources of evidence for Darwin's insights on natural selection and descent with modification of species.

Given the role of language in human social life, and it's magnificent inheritance properties, it was sensible that linguistics would be brought into anthropological science at least in part.  The addition of primatology to the field was also a logical broadening of the comparative basis for understanding our species' evolution.

This is what anthropology was founded to do: to be the natural history science of humankind.  Such an endeavor does not encompass the study of all of human life, and the sciences of sociology and psychology had very different origins.  I will touch briefly on sociology, which is often the most difficult to disambiguate from anthropology.  In contrast to anthropology, sociology was not founded with the fundamental goal of understanding how human social life diversified to what it is today from a series of past mechanistic causes (evolution).  Sociology established itself as strictly the science of social causes for human social life and behavior.  Thus, sociology studied a type of causation that exists at a particular emergent level, just as chemists study the causation of interactions among atoms, and community ecologists study causal interactions among species, etc.  Sociology even today tends to model human social interactions as analogous to particle interactions of physics and with little interest in reducing causal sequences to psychology, biology or physics through a chain of causation; rather, the social causes themselves are of primary interest.  Sociology was always a level of analysis type science, and in that sense more similar to much of modern science (E. O. Wilson has written well on the contrast of natural history science and science practiced at a single emergent level). 

So, that is why anthropology made sense as a distinct discipline.  Does this characterize anthropology today?  Not really.  There are anthropologists (like me) who still are motivated principally by this vision of anthropology as the natural history science of humanity.  I think there has always been at least a small core of anthropologists with this view throughout its 100-150 year existence as a distinct discipline.  However, ever since Franz Boas, many and perhaps most anthropologists have not seen anthropology in this way.  It was Boas who first made popular within anthropology the idea that cultural diversity just springs spontaneously from peoples' heads, and that this construction of culture by ourselves had scarcely anything to do with our biological heritage.  Once anthropologists accepted that, the linkage of fossil diggers, archeologists, and ethnographers in one discipline started to seem incoherent.  This was exacerbated by the increasing popularity of nonscientific methods of cultural analysis that rejected any reconstruction of historical diversification and rejected quantitative methods.  Most of Boas' highly influential students, like Margaret Meade, helped push the discipline in this direction, further splintering anthropology.

What will happen now to anthropology?  I'm not sure, but I am sure that the comparative naturalist science of humanity will be conducted, whether by anthropologists, or some other group of researchers like cultural neuroscientists or psychologists.  This is because there is a real academic discipline at the heart of anthropology.  As we discover more and more about how genes affect our behavior, and even which genetic changes are responsible for our impressive cultural capabilities, the Boasian wall of separation between biological and cultural evolution will become more and more obviously false.  So, someone will take up the effort, because there is a lot of science still to do.
1 Comment
Forward>>

    Author

    This is my personal blog.  The views expressed on this page are my own.  My views should not be taken to represent the views of my mentors, employer, or any person or group other than myself. 

    Archives

    November 2022
    May 2022
    March 2022
    April 2019
    March 2017
    June 2015
    June 2014
    December 2013
    October 2012
    September 2012

    Categories

    All
    Cultural Diffusion
    Cultural Phylogenetics
    Group Selection
    History Of Anthropology
    Kin Selection
    Multilevel Selection
    Neanderthal
    Out Of Africa
    Social Science
    Statistics

    RSS Feed

Powered by Create your own unique website with customizable templates.